Freedom of the will and the highest good.

In Section III of the Groundwork , Kant attempts to prove that the categorical imperative, derived in Section II by the analysis of the concept of free and rational beings in general, actually puts us under an obligation by proving that we are indeed free and rational beings. In his terminology, he wants to show that it is not merely an analytic but a synthetic a priori proposition that our wills are constrained by this imperative. Both the interpretation and the assessment of the arguments by which he proposes to accomplish this remain controversial.
The first claim that Kant makes is that ‘every being who cannot act except under the idea of freedom is just on that account really free in a practical respect, that is, all laws that are inseparably bound up with freedom are valid for it just as if its will were really declared to be free in itself and in theoretical philosophy’, and that every being with a will must indeed act under the idea of freedom (4: 448) (see Will, the ). This seems to mean that agents who conceive of themselves as choosing their own actions, whether or not they conceive of themselves as subject to determinism, do not or perhaps even cannot consider any antecedent determinants of their actions in deciding what to do, but only what now seems most rational to do; thus they must govern their actions by rational and therefore moral laws. This seems right for agents considering their own future actions, but leaves unclear how we are to assess the freedom of the actions of others or even our own past actions.
However, Kant goes on to offer what seems to be a theoretical and therefore general proof of the existence of human freedom. He argues that theoretical philosophy has shown that we must distinguish between considering ourselves as phenomena and noumena, or members of the sensible and the intelligible worlds. From the first point of view, we must consider our actions to be governed by the causality of nature, while in the second, since we cannot consider our actions there to be governed by no law at all, we must consider them to be governed by another kind of causality, namely causality in accord with laws of reason (4: 451-3 ). Thus while our actions appear to be determined by natural causes, in reality they not only can but in fact must accord with laws of reason, hence with the categorical imperative.
There are two problems with this argument. First, it flouts transcendental idealism by assuming positive knowledge about things in themselves. Second, as Henry Sidgwick was to object a century later, it precludes moral responsibility for wrong- doing: if the real laws of our behaviour are necessarily rational and hence moral, any wrong-doing could only show that an agent is not rational, and therefore not responsible, at all.
Whether consciously aware of such objections or not, Kant began to alter his argument for freedom of the will in the Critique of Practical Reason. Here he does not argue from a theoretical proof of our freedom to the fact of our obligation under the moral law, but conversely from our consciousness of that obligation – the ‘fact of reason’ – to our freedom as the necessary condition of our ability and responsibility to fulfil it (5: 29-31). This argument first assumes that transcendental idealism has left open at least the theoretical possibility of freedom of the will, and then depends upon the famous principle ‘ought implies can’ (‘Theory and Practice’, 8: 287 ). Transcendental idealism, of course, seems problematic to many; and although the ‘ought implies can’ principle seems an intuitive principle of fairness, Kant does not actually argue for it. Nevertheless, since this argument assumes only that ‘ought’ implies ‘can‘, it does not imply that any agent who is obliged under the moral law necessarily will act in accordance with it, and thus avoids Sidgwick’s problem about the very possibility of wrong-doing.
Kant depends upon this result in his next major treatment of freedom, in Religion within the Limits of Reason Alone, although there he seems to go too far in the other direction by assuming that evil-doing is not just possible but even necessary. Kant begins this discussion with an elegant account of wrong-doing, arguing that because no human being is simply unaware of the demand of morality – that is implied by the ‘fact of reason’ – acting immorally never comes from mere ignorance of the moral law, but rather from deciding to exempt oneself from this obligation. This position is compatible with the argument for freedom in the second Critique, although not with that of the Groundwork . However, Kant goes on to argue that an evil rather than virtuous choice of fundamental maxim, or ‘radical evil’, is not only possible but inevitable, to be escaped from only by a moral conversion. This doctrine hardly follows from Kant’s previous argument, and seems instead to rest on an odd mixture of empirical evidence and the lingering grip of the Christian doctrine of original sin.
The reality of freedom is only the first of Kant’s three ‘postulates of pure practical reason’; the other two are the existence of God and the immortality of the soul. Again Kant’s argument is that, as the first Critique showed, neither of these can be proven by theoretical metaphysics, but they can nevertheless be postulated as necessary conditions of something essential to morality. In this case, however, they are conditions not of our obligation under the categorical imperative but for the realization of the ‘highest good.’ This is another complex and controversial concept. Kant typically defines it as happiness in proportion to virtue, which is worthiness to be happy (5: 110), but suggests different grounds for the necessity of this conjunction. In the Critique of Practical Reason, Kant sometimes treats happiness and virtue as two separate ends of human beings, one our natural end and the other our moral end, which we simply seek to combine (5: 110). In other places, however, beginning with the ‘Canon of Pure Reason’ in the first Critique, he holds that since what virtue does is precisely to coordinate our mutual pursuit of ends, and happiness arises from the realization of ends, maximal happiness would inevitably follow maximal virtue under ideal circumstances (A 809/B 837 ). Of course, circumstances are not always ideal for morality: as far as we can see, no one achieves perfect virtue in a normal lifespan, and such virtue as is attained is hardly always rewarded with happiness. To counter this, Kant holds that we may postulate immortality, in which to perfect our virtue, and the existence of God, who can legislate a nature in which the ends of virtue are achieved.
This theory has seemed to many to be Kant’s vain attempt to save his personal faith from his own scathing critique of metaphysics. Before such a claim could even be discussed, we would have to know what Kant really means by a postulate of practical reason. Kant gives several hints about this which have not been adequately explored. In the first Critique, he discusses the practical postulates in a section where he considers readiness to bet as a measure of belief, thus suggesting that what he actually has in mind is Pascal’s wager (see Pascal, B.): since there is no theoretical disproof of these postulates, and nothing to lose if they are false, but their value to happiness is great, it is rational to act as if they were true. In a later essay, a draft on the ‘Real Progress of Metaphysics from the Time of Leibniz and Wolff’ from the early 1790s (posthumously published), Kant makes an even more striking suggestion. There he says that in the assumption of the practical postulates ‘the human being is authorized to grant influence on his actions to an idea which he, in accord with moral principles, has made himself, just as if he had derived it from a given object’ (20: 305 ). Here the suggestion is that the practical postulates are nothing less than another expression of human autonomy: not theoretical beliefs at all, let alone religious dogmas, but ideas which we construct for ourselves solely to increase our own efforts at virtue. This idea, that God is in fact nothing but an idea of our own making for use within our moral practice, is a thought Kant repeatedly expressed in his very last years (see §14).

A Kant’s Ethical Theory Revision. What about it?

The Good Will and Duty
In the search for intrinsic ‘good’, Kant did not believe that any outcome was inherently good.  Pleasure or happiness could result out of the most evil acts.  He also did not believe in ‘good’ character traits, as ingenuity, intelligence, courage etc. could all be used for evil.  In fact, he used the term good to describe the ‘good will’, by which he meant the resolve to act purely in accordance with one’s duty.  He believed that, using reason, an individual could work out what one’s duty was.

Free Will, God and Immortality
If our actions are pre-determined and we merely bounce around like snooker-balls, we cannot be described as free and morality doesn’t apply to us.   Kant could not prove that we are free – rather, he presumed that we could act morally, and for this to be the case we must be free.  He also thought that it followed that there must be a God and life after death, otherwise morality would make no sense.

The Categorical Imperative – Universalisability

An imperative is a statement of what should be done.  We have said before that Hume realised you can’t get a should statement out of an is statement.  In other words, experience can only give us hypothetical imperatives (If you want to be healthy, then you should exercise and watch what you eat).  A description of the way the world iscannot tell us the way we should act.
A Categorical Imperative is a should statement, but it is not based on experience, and doesn’t rely on a particular outcome.  Rather, it logically precedes experience, or helps us make sense of experience.   In another area of thinking, Kant showed that we must presume that time moves forwards – our mind imposes this on our experiences to make sense of them.  We therefore could never demonstrate or prove this through experience. 
It is like that with the categorical imperative: certain actions are logically inconsistent and would make no sense as universal laws, such as lying.  As a result, ‘Do not lie’ is a categorical imperative.   This understanding that our mind plays an active role in ordering and shaping our experience was revolutionary, and is Kant’s greatest achievement.
Kant states the categorical imperative as follows:
I ought never to act except in such a way  that I can also will that my maxim should become a universal law.

The Categorical Imperative – Law of Nature
Kant also states the categorical imperative as follows:
Act as if the maxim of your action were to become by your will a universal law of nature.
It is difficult to see how these two statements are different, and many texts treat them as though they say the same thing. However, we think they give a real insight into how Kant perceived the Categorical Imperative

The Categorical Imperative – Ends and means
A good will is one that acts in accordance with rationally-determined duty.  No character trait or consequence is good in itself.  However, as good is defined in terms of rationality, Kant argued that all rational beings were ends in themselves and should never be treated purely as a means to an end.  He put this two different ways:
So act as to treat humanity, whether in your own person or in that of any other, in every case as an end in itself, never as means only.
So act as if you were through your maxims a law-making member of a kingdom of ends.
These latter statements of the Categorical Imperative are really an extension of the statements regarding universalisability – we hold laws if we would will that all other rational beings would also follow them.  As a result, it would be contradictory for any rule to treat a rational being as a means to some greater end: there can be no greater end.  Put another way, I cannot prescribe a rule that, if held by someone else, would result in my being treated merely as a means to end.
The categorical Imperative, stated four different ways above, could be seen as a rational justification for following the golden rule that is the cornerstone of Christian morals (as well as most other religions):   

Love your neighbour as yourself.

Do we understand Kant better than 100 years ago?

From the International Kant Interview, occurred in Moscow in 2005, here are some of the prestigious answers to this challenging question:
Henry Allison: Understanding Kant better than our predecessors: I think that it is inevitable that we think that we do. Indeed, barring historical accidents such as the loss of texts, I do not see how one could even coherently deny it to be the case. (If I were to say that scholars of 100 years ago understood Kant better then we do today, am I not presupposing a certain understanding of Kant which I take to be normative?) One can, of course, say that earlier scholars understood Kant better than some of one`s contemporaries and we clearly all do this; but that`s a different matter.
Nevertheless, that said, I do believe that this has been a particularly fruitful period for Kant-interpretation.
Karl Ameriks: Definitely, and as long as there are no calamities I believe we will continue to understand most figures better as time goes on and we have a better perspective and even more information.

Maria Borges: Yes, because we have access to new Kantian texts, unavailable to philosophers and scholars one century ago. These texts, like the Vorlesungen uber Anthropologie, show another-and fascinating – side of Kant thoughts. We know today that Kant has an a priori moral theory, but also an empirical theory about human nature. We know, for instance, that Kant has a very interesting and sophisticated theory of emotions. He acknowledges that emotions have cognitive and physiological contents. Emotions involve evaluative beliefs and also physiological disturbances. They have an intentional object, they are about something. At the same time, they are accompanied by physiological arousal, what makes them difficult to control. 
Andrew Brook: Hard to say. We know much more about his history, the context in which he worked, his unpublished writings, how he published, and so on than we did 100 years ago. On the other hand, we are twice as far away from actually living in his time. But I am not sure that the question is very relevant. Each generation reinvents Kant to suit its own preoccupations and needs, to some extent. Thus, Kitcher’s Kant is very different from Strawson’s or Bennett’s. The same is true of each language community of Kant scholars. Tugendhat’s Kant is quite different from Kitcher’s.
Allen Wood: Certainly. Even at the most basic level, Kant’s writings are much better known than they were at the time when the Akademie Ausgabe was only beginning to appear. Kant studies is one of the strongest areas in all philosophy, attracting many of the best minds that go into the field. We can expect Kant’s ideas to be even better understood in the future, and the tradition of interpreting Kant still has a great deal to contribute to our understanding of all areas of philosophy, morality and science.

The new kantian Blog

After the success of the Facebook page, and the large number of comments and discussions on the page 
now born this new kantian blog. On this new deck will be offered sometimes the same issues that you will find on the facebook page, and sometimes new topics on which you can freely discuss. We believe that one of the strongest Kantian messages  concern the power and the dignity of an autonomous reason. The respect and the honesty seen in the discussions conducted on the facebook page have convinced us about the foundation of this new page.

We allways think that Immanuel Kant’ mind is still alive because of people able to remember the importance of a free thought and the power of a tenacious reason.  People able to understand that recognize the reason’s limits is honoring its powers. People able to remember that love for the starry sky and esteem for the moral law are the elements that elevate all men but never a man over another. Reading Kant means discover the power of reason humble and proud that, changing the world, rediscovers itself and its infinite value.

Thank you for your visit, enjoy the blog and expose your free thought any time.
 
Thank you all again